A Constructivist Vision of the First-Trimester Abortion Experience
Volume 22/1, June 2020, pp 237 – 250
Sam Rowlands and Jeffrey Wale
Abstract
How might the abortion experience look in a world without the existing regulatory constraints? This paper critically assesses the evidence about how a high-quality abortion experience might be achieved in the first trimester. There would need to be positive obligations on states in pursuance of women’s reproductive rights. The onus would be on states and state actors to justify interferences and constraints upon a woman’s right to terminate in the first trimester of her pregnancy. In this vision, abortion is person-centered and normalized as far as possible. High-quality information about abortion would be freely available through multiple sources and in varying formats. Whenever possible, abortion would happen in a place chosen by the woman, and in the case of medical abortion, could be self-managed with excellent clinical backup on hand should the need arise. The overarching purpose of this paper is to highlight the broader environment and framework of state obligations necessary to underpin the lived experience of abortion.
Introduction
Criminalization of abortion has well-known deleterious effects.1 Much has been written on decriminalization of abortion, specifying what legislation needs to be dismantled.2 In contrast, we adopt a ‘constructivist’ approach, looking at what is needed to support a high-quality abortion experience, drawing upon research and literature that includes the lived experience of women who have undergone abortion. We set aside regulatory constraints that could hinder progress toward giving people with a uterus (in the interest of brevity, ‘women’ is used hereafter) the ability to freely choose how they respond to an unwanted pregnancy. As far as possible, we have used a fresh sheet of paper. We take a ground-up approach, building from scratch and beginning with no abortion-specific laws at all.
Although we use the term ‘abortion’ throughout this paper, we recognize that this may be construed as a loaded term with preconceived connotations. In keeping with our constructivist approach, we use the term simply to denote the steps necessary to bring about the end of an established pregnancy (that is, after implantation of the embryo). These steps would, in the ordinary course of events, result in ending the life of the unborn entity or entities.
Starting points and core assumptions
In this paper, we make several core assumptions. First, we assume that the state has unlimited resources to address its positive and negative obligations to pregnant women. Second, we assume that those resources are distributed fairly, justly, and equally within society. Third, we make no attempt to accommodate the plurality in this vision. There is no sense that competing views require accommodation or that compromises are necessary in the regulatory rules. Fourth, our vision does not seek to erase the private sphere, or any socio-political objections to, or prejudices against abortion. Rather, our focus is on a world without pre-existing regulatory constraint on the choices that women can make in this context. Fifth, although gestation outside the womb may soon be possible (ectogenesis), we assume that some demand for abortion (as currently envisaged) will persist.3 Necessarily, these assumptions limit the transferability of this framework in the real world, but our intention is to encourage policy makers and reformers to think critically about the possibilities that a constructivist approach might offer should the opportunity arise for genuine reform. Further, our purpose is to highlight that in the absence of direct regulatory constraints, it is the broader environment and framework of state obligations that underpin the lived experience of abortion.
Defining quality in abortion care is at an early stage, despite abortion being such a commonplace occurrence. There is no standardized, validated set of quality metrics for abortion as there are, for example, for maternity services.4 This paper does not focus on safety, effectiveness, timeliness, efficiency, and equitability; there is a considerable body of work on these.5 Instead, we concentrate on person-centeredness as a major ingredient of a high-quality abortion experience. Person/patient-centered care means an approach that informs and engages women (and partners, if appropriate) in their own individual health care and also to engage service users in health care service co-design.6 We assume that appropriate regulatory mechanisms remain in place to maintain the safety of all abortion services.7
We do not assume that women will have direct contact with health services. This is in line with current World Health Organization thinking, the general principles of self-care, and the experiences and perceptions of women who have undertaken self-management of medical abortion.8 We do, however, acknowledge that there are still some research gaps on self-managed abortion; for example, how best to inform and support women in using the medicines safely and effectively and how to facilitate the community distribution of high-quality drugs and information.9
We know that many women have opted, for various reasons, for “informal sector” abortions, even when they are entitled to a legal abortion in the formal (approved) health sector.10 On the face of it, this may seem like a second-best option, but as some women positively opt for self-managed abortion at home, it is no longer an act of desperation: “self-managed abortion can be a source of reprieve or escape from … indignities of formal settings and experiences of shame and powerlessness within them.”11 We regard self-managed first-trimester medical abortion (that is without attending a health facility)—following evidence-based regimens using drugs from approved sources, with full information—as safe. Self-management could be supplemented by advice from an approved authority such as a pharmacist or an appropriately trained community activist.
Unless appropriately registered, licensed, and trained, procedures undertaken by informal abortion providers such as herbalists, street vendors, and traditional birth attendants are potentially unsafe. For the avoidance of any doubt, we are not seeking to directly constrain the choices of pregnant women. Rather, our concern is to ensure that women are not harmed or subjected to the unnecessary risk of significant harm by the supply of inaccurate/ inadequate information or the provision of deficient abortion services. Accordingly, we suggest that informal service providers, rather than pregnant women, should be the target of any future regulatory constraints. Our aim is to minimize recourse to untrained service providers by delivering improved access to the formal (approved) and publicly funded sector. In our vision, the formal sector and those who work in it are subject to regulation in relation to the standard and quality of pre-/post-abortion care.
When women are asked what they want in abortion services, they identify minimal delay as a priority.12 Women who have decided to terminate a pregnancy want their abortion procedure to take place as soon as possible, and find a delay distressing.13 Most say they do not want counseling.14 Facilitating access to abortion services is an important aspect of our vision.
Although we do not rule out extension of our vision, we limit the immediate scope of this paper to first-trimester abortion due to the current insufficiency of evidence as to safety, effectiveness, and acceptability of second or third trimester medical abortion undertaken outside the formal health system. Although ambulatory (outpatient) medical abortion is generally limited to 10 weeks’ gestation, the envelope continues to be pushed on this upper limit. The World Health Organization recommends self-managed medical abortion up to 12 weeks’ gestation, conceding that evidence is limited for the upper two weeks.15 Further, we are on slightly easier ethical ground in the first trimester, whether on a rights, personhood, or relational perspective. Our starting point is that state actors have a much harder time justifying constraints on pregnant women during the first trimester, partly because there is more common ground about the moral status of the unborn entity at this stage of development. Consequently, any margin of appreciation that might be granted to states and their agents ought to be narrowly construed during this stage of pregnancy.16
Some of the thinking behind this paper has been stimulated by innovative organizations that provide internet-based abortion services and thereby empower women.17 Although women choose to use these services, the organizations only provide medical abortion and so by definition offer no choice within their service provision. Although the development of drugs for medical abortion has been a revolutionary scientific advance, in many high-resource countries medical abortion now tends to dominate service provision to the exclusion of surgery.18 Surgery obviously requires direct contact with health professionals. But first-trimester surgical abortion can be provided safely outside a hospital setting with simple equipment, and satisfaction with manual vacuum aspiration is high.19 However, unless aspiration is available on demand, it is not a genuine option; for example, a weekly operating list is not sufficient.
The role of the state
All people have the right to expect quality health care from the state. But what exactly are the obligations of the state in pursuance of this right? The reproductive justice framework contends that there is a right to have a child, a right not to have a child, and a right to parent a child in a safe and healthy environment.20 Access to reproductive services is a key component of this framework because “there is no choice where there is no access.”21 Under existing international human rights law, states have specific obligations to respect, fulfill, and protect human rights, including reproductive rights.22 These obligations include limitations on the actions that states may take (negative obligations) and on proactive measures that states must take (positive obligations) to give effect to individual rights and freedoms. States must take steps towards fulfilling their obligations by all appropriate means, including particularly the adoption of legislative measures, and should report on these measures and the basis on which they have been considered the most appropriate under the circumstances.
States have three core obligations relating to abortion: a duty to respect, a duty to fulfill, and a duty to protect. In the following section, we outline how these obligations would work in our vision and offer some framework on scope.
The duty to respect requires states to refrain from interfering directly or indirectly with the enjoyment of reproductive rights unless that interference is justified, proportionate, and necessary to achieve a legitimate aim. Using the work of philosopher John Stuart Mill as our foundation, we argue that interference can only be justified or legitimate if it is necessary to prevent harm to others which is both morally indefensible and rights-violating.23 Unless one subscribes to the view that the unborn entity is a rights-bearer in the first trimester, it would not be legitimate to interfere with a woman’s right to terminate at that stage in order to protect the unborn entity. We do not take an explicit position on such interferences in the later stages of the pregnancy but accept that there might be other legitimate reasons to interfere, or for a state to otherwise take responsibility. For example, where the harm or potential for harm arises from related technology that has been released and managed or controlled in a public health context; or where the dignity of humanity as a whole is at stake; or to preserve/protect the essential pre-conditions for human existence or any social human existence.24 If we take the specific example of prenatal screening, a state may be responsible for the testing technology made available in publicly-funded maternity services. The state may also have reason to intervene where private sector providers promote testing and deselection of specific non-health-related characteristics.25 However, in these cases, the state and their agents would bear a heavy burden to justify any constraint on a woman’s reproductive rights in the context of abortion.
The duty to fulfill requires that states adopt whatever measures are necessary—legislative, budgetary, judicial, and/or administrative—to achieve the full realization of reproductive rights. This would include the provision of appropriate forums to resolve disputes and determine or enforce appropriate remedies. We address the funding of private sector provision below. As part of their obligations, states should ensure that reproductive health information, goods, and services are available, accessible, acceptable, and of good quality: AAAQ.26
The duty to protect requires states to prevent third parties from infringing upon reproductive rights and to take steps to investigate and punish such violations when they occur. So, for example, anyone coercing or misleading a woman into an abortion or covertly inducing an abortion should be subject to some form of regulation. Similarly, any health professional acting in bad faith (for example, failing to obtain adequate consent or delivering poor standards of care) should be subject to some form of sanction. We can debate whether there should be disciplinary, civil, and/or criminal consequences in these circumstances. We should not criminalize human behavior unless absolutely necessary, and then only in a proportionate way. If we choose to direct sanctions against third parties, it may be preferable to use disciplinary or civil mechanisms before engaging the criminal law.
Under its duty to protect, the state should ensure that abortion providers do not infringe upon reproductive rights. Refusals to provide abortion care on grounds of conscience can compromise access to abortion and harm health and well-being.27 Such refusals are not permissible in emergency situations or by institutions; they are only valid in relation to direct provision of care and, in such instances, referral must be made to an alternative willing and capable provider.28 Objector status should be disclosed at an early stage to employers and patients so that timely alternative plans can be made; in all regions of a country there must be adequate numbers of health professionals who provide abortion care and the state must take measures to ensure that women’s access to legal abortion care is not undermined.29 Personal beliefs must not be pursued where they are in conflict with the principles of good medical practice, where they cause patients to be treated unfairly, or where they deny patients access to appropriate treatment or services or cause distress.30
Also, under its duty to protect, the state must ensure that members of the public with anti-choice views, while otherwise being permitted freedom of peaceful assembly, cannot infringe upon reproductive rights using intimidation and harassment close to abortion care facilities.31 Due to the distress women have experienced as a result of protests outside facilities in many countries, safe access zones are an absolute necessity to keep any protests away from facility entrances that women and providers use.
Crisis pregnancy centers are run by non-medical organizations; they attempt to intercept those seeking abortion and persuade them to continue the pregnancy.32 Under its duty to protect, the state must ensure that crisis pregnancy centers do not jeopardize women’s health, disseminate misinformation, and target marginalized groups.33
The essential ingredients that facilitate a positive high-quality abortion experience
In this section, we identify the fundamental ingredients of a positive high-quality abortion experience. Some of these are not applicable to women who self-manage their abortion.
Person-centeredness
In a person-centered approach, care is individualized and tailored to women’s preferences. It is acknowledged that there is no joy in the context of abortion—as with miscarriage and ectopic pregnancy and in stark contrast to childbirth.34 Women can choose how their first-trimester abortion is carried out and their degree of presence; some prefer to be awake and experience it, some prefer to be sedated. Women can have privacy and discreet care; they may fear judgment when grouped with others undergoing abortion.35
The needs and rights of the pregnant woman are at the center of policymaking, information, service delivery, and one-on-one consultations. A person-centered framework and culture supports every person on their journey.36 Person-centeredness was identified as a key dimension of quality health care by the Institute of Medicine and further developed into a framework of eight domains for maternity care by Sudhinaraset et al.; Altshuler and Whaley adapted this structure for abortion care.37 There is inevitably some overlap between these domains. The priority rights at the heart of this framework, and our wider discussion in this section, are the rights to individual autonomy, human dignity, and privacy. Many of our points (including domains 4–8 below) are drawn from these priority rights. This overarching framework is facilitated and realized by engagement of the state duties to respect, fulfill, and protect. The eight domains are:
- Dignity
Dignity refers to the ability of women to receive care in a respectful and caring setting. The care supports an individual’s self-respect. Any perception that this will not be the case can drive women into the informal sector where the informational framework may be less reliable; or they may self-induce abortion without sufficient back-up.
- Autonomy
Human rights considerations dictate that autonomy is the overriding determinant when choices are made in early pregnancy. This takes into account women’s embodied experience of being pregnant. The two basic requirements for autonomy are agency (the capacity for intentional action) and liberty (freedom from controlling influences exerted by external sources).38 Women should have control over their bodies and be free to make choices and decisions without external constraint in the first trimester of their pregnancies. The consent process should be valid. Providers convey to women that they are seen as moral agents, capable of making decisions about their bodies and lives.39
- Privacy
Again, we are not attempting to expunge the distinction between the public and private spheres entirely, although the former is necessarily limited in our vision. Opting for an abortion is an intensely private matter. This includes physical privacy in the treatment setting and the confidentiality of sensitive medical information. Physical examinations should be carried out discreetly. Some women prefer to travel out of their area of residence in order to maintain anonymity. Some may prefer self-managed abortion, perhaps with external support, because it offers greater privacy.
- Communication
Treatment options are fully explained and discussed; women participate actively. The woman’s preferences, needs, and context are taken into account. Non-directive counseling is available, if sought, before and after the procedure or medical administration.
- Support
This needs to be individually tailored as women differ greatly in the degree of support they desire. Some women are grateful not to be questioned too much. Others welcome some acknowledgment of the emotions they are grappling with, or possibly some discussion of them; these might be contradictory emotions (ambivalence) or existential issues that can be triggered, such as life and death, morality, and meaning.40 While some women want to be alone, many value the support of a companion of their choice. Support should extend into the workplace, so that women are guaranteed time off work without probing into their rationale or purpose.41
An important resource for support is the volunteer abortion doula or pregnancy companion. Many doulas are “full spectrum,” meaning they will attend a woman during any pregnancy event, including childbirth.42 Doulas offer compassionate care and are trained to counter stigma. Women overwhelmingly recommend doula support for abortion care, despite the fact that such support is not associated with measurable effects on physical comfort or emotional responses.43 Clinic staff believe doulas contribute to more patient-centered care.44
- Compassionate care
Care is provided in a compassionate manner.45 It is responsive to the person’s specific needs. Such care protects women from distress, pain, or harm. Small gestures can make an enormous difference.46
- Trust
Trust comprises how women assess the delivery of care by a specific provider in terms of their honesty and how confident service users feel about the provider’s competence.
- Health facility environment
This domain includes comfort, cleanliness, adequacy of equipment, and a pleasant environment. As well as the physical environment, this includes human aspects such as a supportive and non-judgemental atmosphere. Women sometimes have preconceived ideas about the appearance of a clinic and may be surprised by the cleanliness of their surroundings or facilities, for example.47 In our vision, there are no Targeted Regulation of Abortion Providers laws (that is, burdensome and medically unnecessary legal requirements that target abortion providers).48 For example, requirements suited to hospital surgical facilities may be imposed which are far in excess of those needed for the relatively ‘low-tech’ nature of abortion procedures.
Normalization
There are two aspects to the normalization of abortion. The first is full integration of abortion into health care as a mainstream service and, more particularly, as part of comprehensive sexual and reproductive health care.49 This should render approved private-sector provision (that is, those not publicly funded) unnecessary, but we would not outlaw these providers unless there were consequential considerations undermining public access. In any event, approved private sector provision would not be available on more favorable terms than public services.
The second is normalization with respect to society. Abortion is mostly subject to negative framing in the media. There are associations with controversy, sensationalism, and immorality.50 There are also associations with ‘deviant’ practices such as teenage pregnancy and undesirable characteristics such as promiscuity; these tend to stereotype and falsely marginalize women who have abortions.51
Despite a broad social narrative that abortion is by default negative, many women undergoing abortion say it is the right choice for them; some even call it a positive experience.52 Language used to describe their experiences can be non-negative but is often intertwined with negative framings. Nevertheless, negativity can be resisted and rejected.
Normalizing representations of abortion can help destigmatize the practice.53 For example, Australian abortion clinic websites unapologetically present “a uniformly clear set of values and practices: a woman’s competency and ownership of decisions relating to her pregnancy; her entitlement to good quality non-judgmental care; and the generally positive effects of an abortion.”54 This establishes “women’s position as the rightful subjects of abortion decisions and constructs abortion as a normal, positive and straightforward procedure that enables women to lead the lives they imagine for themselves.”55
Feminist groups supporting women in self-managed abortion are driving a reduction in stigma. They share a belief “that every person who comes to them has the capacity and right to a safe and dignified abortion informed by the values and needs most important to them.”56
Place of choice
Care closer to home as a means of contributing to the delivery of person-centered care has been in the sight of enlightened health professionals for some years, but unnecessary restrictions have got in the way.57 Absent such restrictions, including those governing where the medicines are administered, a woman can use both mifepristone and misoprostol in the “safety and security” of her home, the home of someone of her choice, or a place of safety.58 She can also choose who is present in that setting to support her. Those conducting their abortion at home need sufficient information that can alert them to medical conditions which would make them high-risk and therefore in need of medical advice and supervision. We would not seek to constrain the choices of the high-risk patient, but we would want to ensure that they were adequately informed and supported. Information provided would also ensure that women understand what symptoms should trigger contact with medical services. A few women request inpatient care because they do not feel safe at home, and this needs to be accommodated.
For those accessing formal health services, we envisage woman obtaining their abortions locally, without extended travel possibly entailing crossing borders.59 Ideally, care could be accessed in a local health center, and at the nearest hospital for those who need hospital care. Special arrangements are needed for sparsely populated areas such as northern Canada and central Australia, and for remote communities with no road/rail links. In such cases, clinicians can provide medical abortion via telemedicine; this service delivery is effective, safe, and has a high satisfaction rating.60
Reproductive health commodity supply and security
In our vision, mifepristone is licensed in all countries. It is currently licensed in only 68 of the 193 countries in the world (35%).61 Our vision would supplant the current situation, in which millions use the less-effective misoprostol-only regimen.
Secure systems are in place for procuring abortion pills and appropriate pregnancy tests for follow-up after abortion from reliable sources: mainly internet-based abortion services and accredited pharmacies.62 These systems would supersede widespread circulation of substandard and counterfeit medicines and other medical products; such medicines include inactive substances, impure products, toxic substances, or other substances entirely.63 Pharmacy supplies can be provided at a distance; an example of regulations applying to such activity is that issued by the UK General Pharmaceutical Council.64
In our vision, over-the-counter status for mifepristone and misoprostol is operational. Only a small amount of additional information would need to be gleaned about self-administration of mifepristone/misoprostol in order to make an application to the US Food and Drug Administration for over-the-counter approval.65 Mechanisms for community pharmacy provision have been elaborated.66
Information
The motto “knowledge is power” has become a cliché but is nevertheless true. Easy access to accurate and clear information is a key element of our vision. Information is supplied in varied forms to suit different individuals. Animated films, as well as pictures and diagrams, supplement the written word.67 Access to this information is in a variety of modes including print, audio, and electronic. Abortion hotlines providing information based on official World Health Organization protocols play an important role. They release reliable information into the public domain where people can share it.68 It is important that relevant information is made available that speaks to all, including any marginalized/intersectional groups and individuals.
What explicit information would be made available? First, the actual choice available would be spelled out. Except where there are medical contraindications, of which there are few, women could freely choose the options of medical or surgical abortion. Early surgical abortion in the form of manual vacuum aspiration is available without delay and not necessarily in a hospital setting.69 Manual vacuum aspiration is available from a range of providers, including nurses, midwives, and general practitioners.70 There are many websites offering science-based information about self-managed medical abortion.
Second, information about local support would be accessible. This includes emotional, social, and financial support.
Third, there would be information about the need for Rhesus disease prophylaxis after 10 weeks’ gestation for those who are Rhesus negative, when antibiotic prophylaxis is recommended, and which medical conditions require special precautions and medical input.71
Fourth, there is good information about what to expect when undergoing an early medical abortion and what human resources can be called upon, such as doulas.72
Finally, information about contraception is freely available, together with the recommended timing of initiation after abortion.73 There is freedom of choice: no disproportionate emphasis on long-acting reversible contraception and no coercion in relation to sterilization.74
Clinical excellence
In our vision, clinicians are still needed to provide expertise in complex medical situations, to provide surgical services, and as a back-up for self-managed medical abortion; the number of such professionals is scaled down by adding a more varied skill mix. Policy makers and managers ensure there are sufficient trained professionals, an even geographical spread of services, hygienic facilities, and ongoing focused capacity building.75 Careful service design ensures availability and accessibility. Waiting times operate according to specified national standards.76 Services are operated in a variety of settings including community facilities.77 Acceptability is continuously monitored.
Telephone advice and emergency consultation at a local medical facility would be available 24 hours a day. Women are given an idea of how much bleeding to expect. The direct experience of pain and bleeding can be distressing and often some discussion and reassurance from an adviser is all that is needed, so direct live contact by phone, video link, or web-based chat is available. Complications are inevitable and experienced staff need to be on hand to deal with these.
Task shifting or sharing optimizes the roles of health care staff.78 Few abortions need to be provided by gynecologists.79 General practitioners play a significant role in service delivery.80 So-called mid-level providers (nurses, midwives, and physician assistants) can safely provide both medical and surgical abortion.81 Pharmacists and pharmacy workers are able to safely provide medical abortion.82
It is envisaged that many women will practice self-care. It has been demonstrated that self-managed early medical abortion is mostly equivalent to that which is medically supervised, in terms of success rates and safety outcomes. Rates of incomplete abortion requiring surgical evacuation are somewhat higher, which may be because of care provision by clinicians with little experience in settings where abortion is legally restricted.83
Women obtain abortion pills through pharmacies or other reliable sources for self-managed abortion.84 Self-care has equal status to clinician-provided care among health and regulatory systems.
Funding
Many studies report financial barriers to access to abortion.85 In our vision, women are not expected to rely on charity for such an important component of health care. Some women will have health insurance which may cover abortion. Although women would be at liberty to pay for private services if they wished to, drugs, materials, and fees are all covered by the state for anyone, regardless of their citizenship status. Such cover is the same for any pregnancy outcome (delivery of any type, miscarriage, or ectopic pregnancy). Travel costs are paid by the state when necessary, for example, for people on state benefits or in a low-income bracket.86
Conclusion
We have proposed a vision where there are obligations on the state in pursuance of women’s reproductive rights under the headings of duties to respect, fulfill, and protect. We recognize that this imagined world is far from current reality and might never be achieved. So, why bother to formulate such a vision? Many of us have spent considerable time addressing the existence and scope of individual rights/freedoms, and on the possible deconstruction of existing regulatory constraints in the context of abortion. We do not besmirch or seek to undermine these efforts. Rather, our central purpose in this paper is to shift attention away from discussions about the lawfulness of abortion. By starting from a world without constraints, the primary focus turns to the environment and framework of state obligations in which abortion services are accessed and delivered. It is these background factors that provide the critical foundation for the realization of individual rights and freedoms. Any reformist agenda should never lose sight of this.
Acknowledgments
We thank Dr. Fiona Bloomer, Professor Sally Sheldon, and Ms. Susan Yanow for commenting on a previous draft of this paper. Any errors remain our own.
Sam Rowlands, LLM, MD, FRCGP, FFSRH is Visiting Professor in the Department of Medical Sciences and Public Health at Bournemouth University, Bournemouth, UK.
Jeffrey Wale, LLB, PhD, PGCE, FHEA, is Senior Lecturer in Law in the Department of Humanities and Law at Bournemouth University, Bournemouth, UK.
Please address correspondence to Sam Rowlands. Email: srowlands@bournemouth.ac.uk.
Competing interests: None declared.
Copyright © 2020 Rowlands and Wale. This is an open access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution Non-Commercial License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0/), which permits unrestricted non-commercial use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original author and source are credited.
References
- J. N. Erdman and R. J. Cook, “Decriminalization of abortion – a human rights imperative,” Best Practice and Research Clinical Obstetrics and Gynaecology 62 (2020), pp. 11-24.
- M. Berer, “Abortion law and policy around the world: in search of decriminalization,” Health and Human Rights Journal 19/1 (2017), pp. 13-27; M. Berer and L. Hoggart, “Progress toward decriminalization of abortion and universal access to safe abortion: National trends and strategies,” Health and Human Rights Journal 21/2 (2019), pp. 79-83.
- N. Hammond-Browning, “A new dawn: Ectogenesis, future children and reproductive choice,” Contemporary Issues in Law 14/4 (2018), pp. 349-373.
- B. G. Darney, B. Powell, K. Andersen, et al., “Quality of care and abortion: Beyond safety,” BMJ Sexual and Reproductive Health 44/3 (2018), pp. 159-160; A. Dennis, K. Blanchard, and T. Bessenaar, “Identifying indicators for quality abortion care: A systematic literature review,” BMJ Sexual and Reproductive Health 43/1 (2017), pp. 7-15.
- World Health Organization, Quality of care: A process for making strategic choices in health systems (Geneva: WHO, 2006); National Institute for Health and Care Excellence, Abortion care NICE guideline [NG140] (London: NICE, 2019); World Health Organization, Safe abortion: Technical and policy guidance for health systems 2nd (Geneva: WHO, 2012).
- A. R. Gagliardi, S. Dunn, A. Foster, et al., “How is patient-centred care addressed in women’s health? A theoretical rapid review,” BMJ Open 9 (2019), p. e026121.
- British Medical Association, How will abortion be regulated in the United Kingdom if the criminal sanctions for abortion are removed? (London: BMA, 2019); J. Herring, E. Jackson, and S. Sheldon, “Would decriminalisation mean deregulation?” in S. Sheldon and K. Wellings (eds) Decriminalising abortion in the UK: What would it mean? (Bristol: Bristol University Press, 2020).
- World Health Organization, WHO consolidated guidelines on self-care interventions for health (Geneva: WHO, 2019); M. Narasimhan, P. Allotey, and A. Hardon, “Self care interventions to advance health and wellbeing: A conceptual framework to inform normative guidance,” BMJ 365 (2019), p. 1688; M. Wainwright, C. J. Colvin, A. Swartz, and N. Leon, “Self-management of medical abortion: A qualitative evidence synthesis,” Reproductive Health Matters 24/47 (2016), pp. 155-167.
- N. Kapp, K. Blanchard, E. Coast, et al., “Developing a forward-looking agenda and methodologies for research of self-use of medical abortion,” Contraception 97/2 (2018), pp. 184-188.
- S. Chemlal and G. Russo, “Why do they take the risk? A systematic review of the qualitative literature on informal sector abortions in settings where abortion is legal,” BMC Women’s Health 19 (2019), p. 55; A. L. Altshuler and N. S. Whaley, “The patient perspective: Perceptions of the quality of the abortion experience,” Current Opinion in Obstetrics and Gynecology 30/6 (2018), pp. 407-413.
- J. N. Erdman, K. Jelinska, and S Yanow, “Understandings of self-managed abortion as health inequity, harm reduction and social change,” Reproductive Health Matters 26/54 (2018), pp. 13-19.
- NICE (see note 5); E. R. Wiebe and S. Sandhu, “Access to abortion: What women want from abortion services,” Journal of Obstetrics and Gynaecology of Canada 30/4 (2008), pp. 327-331; M. R. McLemore, S. Desai, L. Freedman, et al., “Women know best – findings from a thematic analysis of 5,214 surveys of abortion care experience,” Womens Health Issues 24/6 (2014), pp. 594-599.
- J. R. Steinberg, J. M. Tschann, D. Furgerson, and C. C. Harper, “Psychosocial factors and pre-abortion psychological health: The significance of stigma,” Social Science and Medicine 150 (2016), pp. 67-75.
- I. Allen, Counselling services for sterilization, vasectomy and termination of pregnancy (London: Policy Studies Institute, 1985); U. Kumar, P. Baraitser, S. Morton, and H. Massil, “Decision-making and referral prior to abortion: A qualitative study of women’s experiences,” Journal of Family Planning and Reproductive Health Care 30/1 (2004), pp. 51-54; C. Baron, S. Cameron, and A. Johnstone, “Do women seeking termination of pregnancy need pre-abortion counselling?” Journal of Family Planning and Reproductive Health Care 41/3 (2015), pp. 181-185.
- World Health Organization, Medical management of abortion (Geneva: WHO, 2018).
- R. Scott, “Reproductive health: Morals, margins and rights,” Modern Law Review 81/3 (2018), pp. 422-451.
- K. Jelinska and S. Yanow, “Putting abortion pills into women’s hands: Realizing the full potential of medical abortion,” Contraception 97/2 (2018), pp. 86-89; M. Endler, A. Lavelanet, A. Cleeve, et al., “Telemedicine for medical abortion: A systematic review,” BJOG 126/9 (2019), pp. 1094-1102; A. R. A. Aiken, E. Padron, K. Broussard, and D. Johnson, “The impact of Northern Ireland’s abortion laws on women’s abortion decision-making and experiences,” BMJ Sexual and Reproductive Health 45/1 (2019), pp. 3-9.
- A. Popinchalk and G Sedgh, “Trends in the method and gestational age of abortion in high-income countries,” BMJ Sexual and Reproductive Health 45/2 (2019), pp. 95-103.
- G. Dean, P. Cardenas, P. Darney, and A. Goldberg, “Acceptability of manual versus electric aspiration for first trimester abortion; A randomized trial,” Contraception 67/3 (2003), pp. 201-206; L. E. Dodge, L. G. Hoffler, M. R. Hacker, and S. Haider, “Patient satisfaction and wait times following outpatient manual vacuum aspiration compared to electric vacuum aspiration in the operating room: A cross-sectional study,” Contraception and Reproductive Medicine 2 (2017), p. 18.
- Sister Song, Reproductive justice (Atlanta: Sister Song, 2019).
- Ibid.
- For example, see the International Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination Against Women (CEDAW), Article 16. A. Res. 34/180 (1979). Available at: https://www.ohchr.org/EN/ProfessionalInterest/Pages/CEDAW.aspx.
- E. Wicks, The state and the body: legal regulation of bodily autonomy (Oxford: Hart, 2016); J. Feinberg, Moral limits of the criminal law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1984); J.S. Mill, On liberty (London: Penguin, 1982).
- E. Wicks, Ibid; J. Wale, “Regulating disruptive technology and informational interests in the arena of reproductive tests,” Journal of Information Rights, Policy and Practice 3 (2019) http://doi.org/10.21039/irpandp.v3i1.58 ; R. Brownsword and J. Wale, “Testing times ahead: Non-invasive prenatal testing and the kind of community that we want to be,” Modern Law Review 81/4 (2018), pp. 646-672.
- Ibid., Brownsword and Wale.
- UN Economic and Social Council, General comment No. 22 (2016) on the right to sexual and reproductive health (Article 12 of the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights), E/C.12/GC/22. Available at: https://digitallibrary.un.org/record/832961/files/?ln=en.
- P. A. Lohr, J. Lord, and S. Rowlands, “How would decriminalisation affect women’s health?” in S. Sheldon and K. Wellings (eds) Decriminalising abortion in the UK: What would it mean? (Bristol: Bristol University Press, 2020).
- Council of Europe Commissioner for Human Rights, Women’s sexual and reproductive health and rights in Europe (Strasbourg: CoE, 2017).
- Center for Reproductive Rights, Addressing medical professionals’ refusals to provide abortion care on grounds of conscience or religion (New York: CRR, 2018).
- General Medical Council, Personal beliefs and medical practice (London: GMC, 2013).
- P. Lowe and S. Page, “Rights-based claims made by UK anti-abortion activists,” Health and Human Rights Journal 21/2 (2019), pp. 133-144.
- A. G. Bryant and J. J. Swartz, “Why crisis pregnancy centers are legal but unethical,” AMA Journal of Ethics 20/3 (2018), pp. 269-277.
- Holtzman, “Have crisis pregnancy centers finally met their match: California’s Reproductive FACT Act,” Northwestern Journal of Law and Social Policy 12/3 (2017), pp. 78-110.
- A. L. Altshuler, A. Ojanen-Goldsmith, P. D. Blumethal, and L. R. Freedman, “A good abortion experience: A qualitative exploration of women’s needs and preferences in clinical care,” Social Science and Medicine 191 (2017), pp. 109-116.
- Ibid.
- B. McCormack, M. Borg, S. Cardiff, J. Dewing, et al., “Person-centredness – the ‘state’ of the art,” International Practice Development Journal 5 (Suppl 1) (2015), pp. 1-15.
- Committee on Quality of Health Care in America, Institute of Medicine, Crossing the quality chasm: a new health system for the 21st Century (Washington DC: National Academy Press, 2001), Chapter 2, pp. 39-60; M. Sudhinaraset, P. Afulani, N. Diamond-Smith, S. Bhattacharya, et al., “Advancing a conceptual model to improve maternal health quality: The person-centred care framework for reproductive health equity,” Gates Open Research (2017) https://doi.org/10.12688/gatesopenres.12756.1; Altshuler and Whaley (see note 10).
- Wicks (see note 23); T. L. Beauchamp and J. F. Childress, Principles of biomedical ethics, 7th (New York: Oxford University Press, 2013).
- M. Donnelly and C. Murray, “Abortion care in Ireland: Developing legal and ethical frameworks for conscientious provision,” International Journal of Gynecology and Obstetrics 148/1 (2020), pp. 127-132; L. M. Gawron and K. Watson, “Documenting moral agency: A qualitative analysis of abortion decision making for fetal indications,” Contraception 95/2 (2017), pp. 175-180.
- M. Stålhandske, M. Ekstrand, and T. Tydén, “Women’s existential experiences within Swedish abortion care,” Journal of Psychosomatic Obstetrics and Gynecology 32/1 (2011), pp. 35-41; A. Kero, “Psychosocial factors in women requesting abortion,” in S. Rowlands (ed) Abortion care (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2014), pp. 34-41.
- J. Devlin Trew, F. K. Bloomer, C. Pierson, et al., Abortion as a workplace issue: A trade union survey North and South of Ireland (Dublin: UNITE, 2017).
- J. Chor, V. Goyal, A. Roston, et al., “Doulas as facilitators: The expanded role of doulas into abortion care,” Journal of Family Planning and Reproductive Health Care 38/2 (2012), pp. 123-124; A. Basmajian, “Abortion doulas,” Anthropology Now 6/2 (2014), pp. 44-51.
- J. Chor, B. Hill, S. Martins, S. Mistretta, et al., “Doula support during first-trimester surgical abortion: A randomized controlled trial,” American Journal of Obstetrics and Gynecology 212/1 (2015), pp. 45.e1-45.e6; J. Chor, P. Lyman, M. Tusken, et al., “Women’s experiences with doula support during first-trimester surgical abortion: A qualitative study,” Contraception 93/3 (2016), pp. 244-248; S. F. Wilson, E. P. Gurney, M. D. Sammel, and C. A. Schreiber, “Doulas for surgical management of miscarriage and abortion: A randomized controlled trial,” American Journal of Obstetrics and Gynecology 216/1 (2017), pp. 44.e1-44.e6.
- J. Chor, P. Lyman, J. Ruth, et al., “Integrating doulas into first-trimester abortion care: Physician, clinic staff, and doula experiences,” Journal of Midwifery and Women’s Health 63/1 (2018), pp. 53-57.
- R. Bivins, S. Tierney, and K. Seers, “Compassionate care: Not easy, not free, not only nurses,” BMJ Quality and Safety 26/12 (2017), pp. 1023-1026.
- K. Kimport, K. Cockrill, and T. A. Weitz, “Analyzing the impacts of abortion clinic structures and processes: A qualitative analysis of women’s negative experience of abortion clinics,” Contraception 85/2 (2012), pp. 204-210.
- McLemore (see note 12).
- N. Austin and S. Harper, “Assessing the impact of TRAP laws on abortion and women’s health in the USA: A systematic review,” BMJ Sexual and Reproductive Health 44/2 (2018), pp. 128-134.
- Altshuler and Whaley (see note 10).
- C. Purcell, S. Hilton, and L. McDaid, “The stigmatisation of abortion: A qualitative analysis of print media in Great Britain in 2010,” Culture, Health and Sexuality 16/9 (2014), pp. 1141-1155.
- Ibid.
- C. Purcell, K. Maxwell, F. Bloomer, et al., “Towards normalising abortion: Findings from a qualitative secondary analysis study,” Culture, Health and Sexuality (2020) https://doi.org/10.1080/13691058.2019.1679395.
- Ibid; B. Baird and E. Millar, “More than stigma: Interrogating counter narratives of abortion,” Sexualities 22/7-8 (2019), pp. 1110-1126.
- Baird and Millar (see note 53).
- Ibid.
- Erdman, Jelinska and Yanow (see note 11).
- Lohr, Lord, and Rowlands (see note 27); K. Guthrie, “Care closer to home,” Best Practice and Research Clinical Obstetrics and Gynaecology 24/5 (2010), pp. 579-591.
- Lohr, Lord, and Rowlands (see note 27); K. Broussard, “The changing landscape of abortion care: Embodied experiences of structural stigma in the Republic of Ireland and Northern Ireland,” Social Science and Medicine 245 (2020), p. 112686.
- J. Barr-Walker, R. T. Jayaweera, A. M. Ramirez, and C. Gerdts, “Experiences of women who travel for abortion: A mixed methods systematic review,” PLoS ONE 14 (2019), p. e0209991; C. Sethna and G. Davis, Abortion across borders (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 2019).
- R. Gill and W. V. Norman, “Telemedicine and medical abortion: Dispelling safety myths with facts,” Mhealth 4 (2018), p. 3; M. Endler, A. Cleeve, and K. Gemzell-Danielsson, “Online access to abortion medications: A review of utilization and clinical outcomes,” Best Practice and Research Clinical Obstetrics and Gynaecology 63 (2020), pp. 74-86; J. E. Kohn, J. L. Snow, H. R. Simons, et al., “Medication abortion provided through telemedicine in four U.S. states,” Obstetrics and Gynecology 134/2 (2019), pp. 343-350; E. Raymond, E. Chong, B. Winikoff, et al., “TelAbortion: Evaluation of a direct to patient telemedicine abortion service in the United States,” Contraception 100/3 (2019), pp. 173-177.
- Mifepristone approvals (New York: Gynuity, 2019).
- WHO (see note 15); S. Cameron, S. Rowlands, and K. Gemzell-Danielsson, “Self-assessment of success of early medical abortion using a self-performed urine pregnancy test,” European Journal of Contraception and Reproductive Health Care 24/4 (2019), pp. 319-321.
- World Health Organization, WHO global surveillance and monitoring system for substandard and falsified medical products (Geneva: WHO, 2017); S. Rowlands. “Abortion pills: Under whose control?” Journal of Family Planning and Reproductive Health Care 38/2 (2012), pp. 117-122.
- General Pharmaceutical Council, Guidance for registered pharmacies providing pharmacy services at a distance, including on the internet (London: GPC, 2015).
- Kapp, D. Grossman, E. Jackson, et al., “A research agenda for moving early medical pregnancy termination over the counter,” BJOG 124/11 (2017), pp. 1646-1652.
- Raifman, M. Orlando, S. Rafie, and D. Grossman, “Medication abortion: Potential for improved patient access through pharmacies,” Journal of the American Pharmacists Association 58/4 (2018), pp. 377-381.
- S. Sherman, J. Harden, D. Cattanach, and S. Cameron, “Providing experiential information on early medical abortion: A qualitative evaluation of an animated personal account, Lara’s Story,” Journal of Family Planning and Reproductive Health Care 43/4 (2017), pp. 269-273.
- Erdman, Jelinska and Yanow (see note 11).
- A. B. Goldberg, G. Dean, M. Kang, et al., “Manual versus electric vacuum aspiration for early first-trimester abortion: A controlled study of complication rates,” Obstetrics and Gynecology 103/1 (2004), pp. 101-107; R. J. Lyus, P. Gianutsos and M. Gold, “First trimester procedural abortion in Family Medicine,” Journal of the American Board of Family Medicine 22/2 (2009), pp. 169-174.
- S. Yanow, “Is it time to integrate abortion into primary care,” AJPH 103/1 (2013), pp. 14-16; S. Sheldon and J. Fletcher, “Vacuum aspiration for induced abortion could be safely and legally performed by nurses and midwives,” Journal of Family Planning and Reproductive Health Care 43/4 (2017), pp. 260-264; S. J. Jejeebhoy, S. Kalyanwala, A. J. F. Zavier, et al., “Can nurses perform manual vacuum aspiration (MVA) as safely and effectively as physicians? Evidence from India,” Contraception 84/6 (2011), pp. 615-621.
- NICE (see note 5).
- Wainwright, Colvin, Swartz, and Leon (see note 8).
- S. Rowlands and K. Gemzell-Danielsson, “Postabortion contraception,” European Journal of Contraception and Reproductive Health Care 22/2 (2017), pp. 162-163.
- S. Rowlands and J. Wale, “Sterilisations at delivery or after childbirth: Addressing continuing abuses in the consent process,” Global Public Health 14/8 (2019), pp. 1153-1166.
- M. Vekemans, U. de Souza, and M. Hurwitz, Access to safe abortion: A tool for assessing legal and other obstacles (London: International Planned Parenthood Federation, 2008).
- NICE (see note 5).
- National Institute for Health and Care Excellence, Abortion care guideline evidence review. [A] Accessibility and sustainability of abortion services (London: NICE, 2019).
- World Health Organization, WHO recommendations: Optimizing health worker roles to improve access to key maternal and newborn health interventions through task shifting (Geneva: WHO, 2012).
- Lohr, Lord and Rowlands (see note 27).
- A. J. Lawson, R. Nichols, D. Bateson, et al., “Medical termination of pregnancy in general practice in Australia: A descriptive-interpretive qualitative study,” Reproductive Health 14 (2017), p. 39; J. Dressler, N. Maughn, J. A. Soon, and W. V. Norman, “The perspective of rural physicians providing abortion in Canada: Qualitative findings of the BC Abortion Providers Survey (BCAPS),” PLoS ONE 8 (2013), p. e67070; S. Gaudu, M. Crost, and L. Esteria, “Results of a 4-year study on 15,447 medical abortions provided by privately practicing general practitioners and gynecologists in France,” Contraception 87/1 (2013), pp. 45-50.
- S. Barnard, C. Kim, M. H. Park, and T. D. Ngo, “Doctors or mid-level providers for abortion,” Cochrane Database of Systematic Reviews (2015), CD011242; K. Gemzell-Danielsson and H. Kopp Kallner, “Mid-level providers,” in S. Rowlands (ed) Abortion care (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2014), pp. 219-226.
- A. Tamang, M. Puri, S. Masud, et al., “Medical abortion can be provided safely and effectively by pharmacy workers trained within a harm reduction framework: Nepal,” Contraception 97/2 (2018), pp. 137-143.
- Endler, Lavelanet, Cleeve et al (see note 17); D. Grossman, “Telemedicine for medical abortion – time to move towards broad implementation,” BJOG 126/9 (2019), p. 1103.
- Jelinska and Yanow (see note 17); Rowlands (see note 63).
- NICE (see note 77).
- NICE (see note 5).